Their commitment to D&I
is all too often treated as a self-evident truth that none should be allowed to
question in public discourse. But this new consensus for D&I, if left
unchallenged, has an unintended consequence: unthinking intellectual rigidity,
a malaise that all successful institutions must guard against.
The first difficulty with D&I is that it says very
little about whom to admit and whom to exclude. Scarcity of places is a major
constraint, so any institution committed to D&I has to decide whom to
exclude from its community. Ironically, these institutions depend for their
success on the institution of private property, which gives them the breathing
room on which their cooperative activities rest. Defenders of D&I
constantly bewail the bogeyman of exclusion, but no one is suggesting that
these D&I stalwarts should select their new students and employees at
random, in order to spare every poor soul from the heavy burden of being turned
down on the merits. Institutions pursuing D&I necessarily have to adopt
policies that privilege some people at the expense of others.
Having chosen its members, D&I champions next embrace
a message of
“fairness and protection to all regardless of gender, race, religion, ethnicity
or sexual orientation.” But rarely do they face up to the conceptual
ambiguities and practical tradeoffs that this grandiose statement conceals.
Does any organization welcome the individual who is bold enough to reject
D&I? More concretely, does D&I make accommodations for employees or
students who on bona fide religious grounds are opposed to same-sex marriage?
More generally, does D&I embrace, or even tolerate, true intellectual and
political diversity? If so, why are there, from top to bottom, so few
Republicans or libertarians within their diverse and inclusive ranks? Or does D&I
unwisely overvalue skin-deep diversity at the expense of the necessary technical
skills needed for particular jobs, like computer programming? D&I supporters
pretend that these inescapable trade-offs do not exist: indeed, they all too
often take pride in demonizing and excluding those who disagree with them.
In addition, the defenders of D&I too often insist that
what works for them must work for everyone else. To be sure, most organizations
function best when their members share common goals. Accordingly, large
commercial firms often justify the importance of diversity in order to better
serve their global clientele. In some contexts, they have made exactly the
right judgment. Firm members and employees have to be comfortable dealing with
all sorts of coworkers, customers, and contractors from the four corners of the
globe.
By the same token, however, too much difference and
variation in the workplace can come at a cost as well, undermining the shared
sense of mission necessary for organizational success. Unfortunately, the D&I
movement downplays the only two ways to deal with these internal conflicts,
both of which involve exclusion. The first way is for a firm to acknowledge
that certain disagreements cannot be papered over and, therefore, to make
accommodations so that members of different religious groups, for example, can
pray in separate places. Alternatively, if these differences prove too acute,
the whole enterprise can completely split into different firms with more
homogenous memberships. These newly divided groups can then interact with each
other, if they so choose, by trading goods and services through discrete
transactions that do not require the common vision needed within a single firm.
The need for business segmentation thus undercuts claims
that the D&I template works universally. Thus smaller firms with specific
religious or political ends have to reject the D&I formula. Regrettably, D&I
defenders have become ugly in their willingness to resort to government force
to compel adherence by others to their cherished norm. They are all too happy with enforcing a
so-called “human rights” law that tells religious individuals to close up shop
if they refuse to supply flowers, pictures, or wedding cakes to same-sex
marriages. That totalitarian excess rests on the bizarre notion that a
competitive market cannot function unless every firm agrees to serve every
customer. Not so. Competition is dynamic, so if any one firm exits a segment of
the market, others will move in to the void. No one thinks that gay activists
must be obliged to help organize the weddings of evangelicals. Why not the
converse? In the absence of any monopoly power, cooperation through trade
yields more economic gain and civic peace than the majority’s efforts to make
all dissenters bend to their will. Live-and-let-live is essential for social
peace.
This same intolerant frame of mind can exist in both public
and private universities. The unfortunate 2010 decision of the United States
Supreme Court in Christian Legal
Society v. Martinez held that the Hastings Law School could deny
to the small and outnumbered Christian Legal Society certain key services
because of its religious opposition to same-sex marriage and its refusal to
allow gays and lesbians into its membership, effectively gutting the
organization. At one time, the Supreme Court was sensitive to the plight of “discrete
and insular minorities,” but in the new age of D&I conformity, both
courts and former civil libertarians refuse to accommodate outnumbered and
outgunned religious minorities, so that they may practice their faith in peace.
The same intolerance is similarly all too prevalent in
private institutions. Some time ago I wrote about the perverse decision of
Harvard University to force its “final clubs” (essentially, fraternities and
sororities) to become coed by preventing any man or woman who joined an
all-male or all-female club from holding any leadership role “in recognized
student organizations or athletic teams”—even though virtually all sports teams
are single sex.
Recently, Harvard went one step farther, decreeing that, effective for the entering class of 2018, it will not allow anymore students to join the final clubs, including those that recently went coed under massive administrative pressure. The reason Harvard adopted this radical policy was to counter what it deemed to be the corrosive and toxic influence that these clubs exerted on campus. Once again, the champions of D&I have found it unacceptable to allow any student to belong to any group that failed to conform to Harvard’s singular vision of the social good.
By why this exercise of raw power? At no point did the
Harvard report setting
out this new policy demonstrate how membership in these clubs created the
terrible conditions that were attributed to them. Instead, the sanctimonious
and slapdash report rests on a general observation that is easy to make but
impossible to refute, namely, that the “pernicious” effects of these
organizations “permeate the fabric of campus culture.” The 2017 report offered
no evidence of any untoward incidents at the clubs, nor did it show that
members behaved in a haughty or disrespectful manner toward others. Further,
there was no effort to show that these clubs, which have gained membership in
recent years, were somehow rejected en masse by the student body—who, in a
recent referendum, rejected the earlier sanctions against the clubs by about a
two-to-one vote.
The self-selected doubters have every moral right not to
join these clubs, but no moral right to impose their puritanical views on
others. By taking this draconian action against the clubs, Harvard has made
itself a less diverse place, stifling intellectual and political disagreements.
As the Supreme Court, has noted in one of its most lucid
moments, the offense, however great, that one person takes towards another
is never a warrant to drown their speech or ideas. The same attitude that
applies to speech should apply to the offense that people take to all forms of
peaceful conduct. Freedom of association requires both the power to exclude and
to include.
I believe that as a private institution, Harvard can adopt
whatever foolish policy it chooses. But it will pay a heavy price for its own
dogmatic intolerance. Its pursuit of “diversity” in this form can result only
in drab conformity, from which it excludes all those who don’t share its
vision. As the racial and religious composition of the United States changes, a
pursuit of excellence will quickly lead to a different composition of students
at many universities and many firms. But different institutions may choose to
follow different approaches, and the great virtue of a competitive market is
that it allows natural experiments to determine which approaches work and which
do not. Harvard is already lurching toward mediocrity in its relentless pursuit
of ideological conformity. Its blunders should be a wake-up call to everyone
else.
Professor Richard A. Epstein, the Peter and Kirsten Bedford
Senior Fellow at the Hoover Institution, is the Laurence A. Tisch Professor of
Law, New York University Law School, and a senior lecturer at the University of
Chicago. This article was first
published by the Hoover Institute's Defining
Ideas.
No comments:
Post a Comment